• Nu S-Au Găsit Rezultate

(1)Journal for the Study of Religions and Ideologies, vol

N/A
N/A
Protected

Academic year: 2022

Share "(1)Journal for the Study of Religions and Ideologies, vol"

Copied!
25
0
0
Arată mai multe ( pagini)

Text complet

(1)

Journal for the Study of Religions and Ideologies, vol. 15, issue 43 (Spring 2016): 3-27.

ISSN: 1583-0039 © SACRI

W

ITTGENSTEIN

: F

ROM A

R

ELIGIOUS

P

OINT OF

V

IEW

?

Abstract: Wittgenstein’s remark to Drury that he looks at philosophical problems from a religious point of view has greatly puzzled commentators. The paper argues that the readings given by commentators Malcolm, Winch and Labron are illuminating, but inadequate. Second, using Wittgenstein’s “use-conception of meaning” as an example, the paper proposes a more adequate reading that emphasizes Wittgenstein’s view that

“nothing is hidden” (Philosophical Investigations, para. 435). In this connection, the paper examines Fodor’s critique of Wittgenstein’s “use-conception” and shows how Fodor only refutes a “misuse-conception meaning” because he presupposes a kind of linguistic meaning, the kind that Wittgenstein emphasizes, that is “already before his eyes” (and, therefore, prior to Fodor’s theories of meaning). Wittgenstein’s view that the truth is already before one’s eyes is further explained by employing an ethical analogy with Raskolnikov’s enlightenment in Dostoevsky’s Crime and Punishment. Finally, the paper addresses the difficult question whether Wittgenstein is, despite his own denials, “a religious man”, and argues that there is a non-trivial religious dimension in Wittgenstein’s life but that there are several important senses in which Wittgenstein is correct that he is not a religious person.

Key Words: Wittgenstein, Malcolm, religious point of view, Genesis, use-conception of meaning, unconcealedness, phenomenology, Dostoevsky, ethics.

Richard McDonough

Arium Academy, School of Arts and Sciences, Republic of Singapore.

Email: [email protected]; [email protected]

(2)

Journal for the Study of Religions and Ideologies, vol. 15, issue 43 (Spring 2016) 4 When Wittgenstein was working on the latter part of the Philosophical Investigations, he said to his … close friend … Drury: … “I am not a religious man but I cannot help seeing every problem from a religious point of view.” … [This]

made Drury wonder whether “there are not dimensions to Wittgenstein’s thought that are still largely being ignored”... I have the same doubt [about] myself.

Norman Malcolm, Wittgenstein: From a Religious Point of View? (1)1

Wittgenstein’s remark to Drury (hereafter WRD) that he cannot help seeing “every problem”, by which he clearly includes philosophical problems, from a religious point of view is puzzling.2 Drury implies, and Malcolm concurs, that WRD suggests that there may be entire

“dimensions” to Wittgenstein’s “later philosophy” (hereafter WittgensteinLP) that are still not understood.3 The present paper attempts to clarify WRD by showing how it applies to WittgensteinLP’s central view in his Philosophical Investigations, his “use-conception” of meaning. The

“use-conception” includes WittgensteinLP’s view that linguistic meaning (hereafter, meaningL) is not caused by hidden processes in the brain or mind because it is “already in plain view” in the public uses of words.4 It is argued that WittgensteinLP’s use-conception of meaningL, properly understood, illustrates his real point in WRD.

The first section argues that Shields’, Malcolm’s, Winch’s and Labron’s readings misconstrue WittgensteinLP’s point in WRD.5 The second discusses WittgensteinLP’s picture of the genesis of meaningL. The third explains Wittgenstein’sLP notion of the unhidden character of meaningL.6 The fourth explains the religious point of view in Wittgenstein’sLP account of meaningL. The fifth provides an ethical analogue of Wittgenstein’sLP view in WRD. The sixth argues that WittgensteinLP is, by his own criterion of religiosity, not a religious man but that he would likely be judged to be religious by the more ordinary person’s criteria, and, for this latter reason, there may be an element of truth in Malcolm’s, Winch’s and Labron’s views after all (although it must be stated carefully).

The Standard Readings of Wittgenstein’s Remark to Drury

[Malcolm] explicitly disclaimed any pretensions to finality or certainty in hisinterpretations.… I want to make the same sort of disclaimer.

Peter Winch, “Discussion of Malcolm’s Essay” (132)

Before considering Malcolm’s, Winch’s, and Labron’s readings of WRD it is useful to examine Shields’ account of logic and sin in Wittgenstein’s views.7 Shields’ reading is less relevant here because he is concerned primarily with Wittgenstein’s early philosophy (hereafter WittgensteinEP), whereas Malcolm et al are concerned primarily with WittgensteinLP. For, although there is some continuity between Wittgenstein’s early and later

(3)

Journal for the Study of Religions and Ideologies, vol. 15, issue 43 (Spring 2016) 5 philosophies in this respect there are major differences as well. This is illustrated by Shield’s title, Logic and Sin in the Writings of Ludwig Wittgenstein. Though Shields’ emphasis on logic is entirely natural for WittgensteinEP it is strained for WittgensteinLP. Though WittgensteinLP does not eschew logic altogether, he does seem to demote it in status:

[W]hat we call “sentence” and “language” has not the kind of formal unity that I imagined, but that it is a family of structures more or less closely related to each other. But what becomes of logic now? Its rigour seems to be giving way here.8

Thus, Labron correctly points out that Shields misses the unique character of WittgensteinLP’s views by seeing it “within a Tractarian framework,” e.g. WittgensteinLP’s emphasis on “philosophical grammar”

and “forms of life” elude Shields’ treatment.9 This does not mean Shields’

work is irrelevant. He shows that WittgensteinEP saw philosophical mistakes as akin to sin — which prefigures WittgensteinLP’s conception of philosophical sin.10 Though Shield’s view of the religious point of view in WittgensteinEP cannot shed direct light on WittgensteinLP’s view in WRD, it shows that Wittgenstein’s views on the religious aspect of philosophical views traces to his early philosophy.

Consider now Malcolm’s reading of WRD,

[T]here are four analogies between Wittgenstein’s conception of the grammar of a language and his

view of what is paramount in a religious life.

First, in both, there is an end to explanation;

second, in both there is an inclination to be amazed

at the existence of something; third, into both there enters the notion of an ‘illness’; fourth, in both

doing, acting, takes priority over intellectual under- standing and reasoning.11

Before one considers Malcolm’s four analogies, note that WRD does not assert any analogies between WittgensteinLP’s conception of the grammar of a language and “what is paramount in religious life”.12 WRD does not mention grammar, what is paramount in religion or religious

“life” at all. Malcolm here reads into WRD what he takes to be typical WittgensteinLP themes. But if one attends strictly to what WRD says, as opposed to what one believes WittgensteinLP should say about such

“analogies”, WRD states simply that WittgensteinLP looks at such problems

“from a religious point of view”.13 The notion of grammar and forms of religious life do figure into WittgensteinLP’s resolution of those problems but WRD makes no reference to WittgensteinLP’sway of resolving problems.

WRD only refers to his way of viewing the problems. Malcolm runs these together. To be sure, it would be surprising if there were not some link

(4)

Journal for the Study of Religions and Ideologies, vol. 15, issue 43 (Spring 2016) 6 between WittgensteinLP’s way of viewing problems and his way of resolving them, but in order to conceive that link properly one must be clear what is and what is not strictly stated in WRD.

Towards this end, consider now the four analogies Malcolm offers between philosophical problems and “what is paramount in a religious life”. Note first that all four of Malcolm’s analogies are quite vague. There are many domains that share in these analogies but have nothing to do either with philosophy or with “religious life”. One can imagine examples from various disciplines14, but I employ examples from social psychology.

Malcolm’s first analogy is that in WittgensteinLP’s conception of the grammar of a language and in his view of what is paramount in a religious life there is an end to explanation. But this is also found in social psychology.

Studies show that for identical twins nurtured in the same environment there is some (33% for males and 23% for females) concordance between gender identity disorders in the two twins15. But why is the correlation different for males and females and why is the concordance in cases of similar growth environment not perfect? Social psychologists are not surprised: “That’s just the way it is. Explanations come to an end somewhere.”16

Malcolm’s second analogy is that in WittgensteinLP’s conception of the grammar of a language and in his view of religious life there is an inclination to be amazed at the existence of something. This too is found in social psychology. Most of the children from a certain deprived area in India end up in obscurity, but a boy named Ramanujan with virtually no formal training in mathematics becomes a recognized mathematical genius who has been compared with Euler17. At age 17 he was regarded by his peers “with respectful awe”18 and many professional mathematicians felt the same.

Malcolm’s third analogy is that “into both there enters the notion of an ‘illness’”. But this too is found in social psychology. For example, many scholars have remarked on the connection between genius and madness.

Kottler considers 10 such cases but there are many more that he could have considered19. This is a natural example because WittgensteinLP does compare philosophical errors to an illness20. But Malcolm provides no explanation what particular point Wittgenstein intends by bringing in the

“religious point of view” in WRD that could not be accomplished by the illness-comparison alone.

Finally, Malcolm claims as his fourth analogy that “in both doing (acting) takes priority over intellectual understanding and reasoning”. But this too is true in social psychology where it often happens that certain techniques show good clinical results despite the fact that no one understands “the mechanism of action”21. In practical areas of social psychology, the fundamental aim is to cure the patient. It would be preferable to understand how the technique works but, if no one does, it will often be used anyways.

(5)

Journal for the Study of Religions and Ideologies, vol. 15, issue 43 (Spring 2016) 7 Although Malcolm is no doubt correct that there are analogies between WittgensteinLP’s notion of the grammar of a language and religious life, his account of the analogies is too broad in that it applies to social psychology as well. Further, one could easily develop further examples from literature, physics, sports etc. Malcolm’s grid is simply not fine-grained enough to capture the point in WRD.

Winch’s remarks are also problematic. First, Winch admits that “we should not expect a very clear-cut account of what Wittgenstein meant”.22 Most of Winch’s remarks are criticisms of Malcolm’s views, but he admits he is not sure how deep these go.23 Winch’s positive alternative to Malcolm’s reading is sketchy but he does make several points.24 Since WittgensteinLP had deep respect for Kierkegaard,25 Winch attempts to explain WRD by comparing Kierkegaard’s concept of religious faith as a passion with the passion in WittgensteinLP’s writings.26 However, WRD does not say that WittgensteinLP considers philosophical problems with religious passion. It says that he looks at philosophical problems from a

“religious point of view” (which sounds more conceptual than emotional).

After pointing out how Malcolm misinterprets WRD by reading into it notions that are not there, Winch errs in the same way.

Labron supports Malcolm’s vision of an analogy between WittgensteinLP’s views and religious points of view, but Labron goes further and asserts an analogy between WittgensteinLP’s thought and Hebraic, as opposed to Greek, thought.27 Labron cites one of WittgensteinLP’s remarks to Drury in support of his reading:

Your [Drury’s] religious ideas have always seemed to me more Greek than Biblical … [w]hereas my thoughts are one hundred percent Hebraic.28

However, this passage refers to Wittgenstein’s “religious ideas”.

WittgensteinLP’s statement that his religious ideas are Hebraic rather than Greek does not imply that his philosophical views are Hebraic rather than Greek. Indeed, WittgensteinLP elsewhere expresses considerable sympathy for Greek philosophy: “Wittgenstein reads Plato—the only philosopher he reads”.29 WittgensteinLP’s remark to Bouwsma may be exaggerated but it is clear that WittgensteinLP’s philosophical outlook does not reject Greek ideas tout court in favour of Hebrew ideas. Once again, WRD does not say that WittgensteinLP looks at philosophical problems from any particular religious viewpoint, as if WittgensteinLP might have meant that he looks at philosophical problems from a Buddhist or a Hindu point of view. Winch is correct that many passages in WittgensteinLP make clear that “the phrase ‘from a religious point of view’ [in WRD] cannot be interpreted in terms of any particular theological doctrine,”30 e.g., Wittgenstein is not developing a philosophyfrom a Christian, Jewish, or Hindu point of view.

In summary, Malcolm, Winch and Labron all make useful points, but each reads ideas into WRD that are simply not there. WRD does not assert

(6)

Journal for the Study of Religions and Ideologies, vol. 15, issue 43 (Spring 2016) 8 any analogy between Wittgenstein’s philosophical views and religious views. It certainly does not mention any particular religious point of view (the Hebraic). Neither does WRD say that Wittgenstein pursues philosophical views with Kierkegaard-like religious passion. Malcolm, Winch and Labron, despite many useful insights, are clearly struggling to come to terms with WRD.

In fact, one obtains a far better model of Wittgenstein’s meaning in WRD in the following analogy with Kant. The first formulation of Kant’s categorical imperative in his Grounding for the Metaphysics of Morals is: "Act only according to that maxim whereby you can at the same time will that it should become a universal law without contradiction.”31 Consider moral subject S attempting to decide whether it is morally right to act on maxim M (that one should always tip waiters). Kant enjoins S to make a rather audacious Gedankenexperiment, namely, to imagine his/herself in the position of the creator of universe U and ask him/herself whether they could consistently will that M is a universal law of nature in U. Kant enjoins S to look at their moral problem from a kind of religious point of view—that of the creator. When Kant suggests this, it is not because he believes there is actually any analogy between S’s mundane problem whether to tip waiters and religious issues (let alone “paramount”

religious issues). Kant enjoins S to engage in this audacious thought- experiment because he believes that doing so suggests a useful new perspective on S’s moral problem. This new perspective, however unrealistic, helps S see the problem in new light. Thus, Kant does not see actual analogies between creating universes and tipping waiters but only urges one to adopt a point of view that sheds light on the moral problem.32 This Kantian model, which is also conceptual rather than passionate, provides a far better model of WRD than those offered by Malcolm, Winch or Labron.

The Genesis of Meaning

If I am inclined to suppose that a mouse has come into being by spontaneous generation out of grey rags and dust, I shall do well to examine

those rags very closely to see how a mouse may have hidden in them, … But if I am convinced that a mouse cannot have come into being from these things then this investigation will [seem] superfluous. [W]e must … understand what it is that opposes such an examination of details in philosophy.

Ludwig Wittgenstein, Philosophical Investigations (52)

In PI WittgensteinLP employs a peculiar image, i.e. the spontaneous generation of a mouse from “grey rags and dust,” to shed light on a philosophical problem.33 In PI (51) the problem is how the meaningL of words is determined by “the technique of using words”.34 Thus, the mouse in PI (52) is, so to speak, “the mouse of meaningL” and the “grey rags and dust” are the chaotic uses of words in natural languages. Thus, PI (52) is

(7)

Journal for the Study of Religions and Ideologies, vol. 15, issue 43 (Spring 2016) 9 considering whether meaningL arises spontaneously from chaos of everyday linguistic usage.35 But PI (52) also suggests that if one thinks that this does happen, one should look closely to see whether meaningL is somehow hidden in those chaotic uses of words—the point being that meaningL is not really hidden there but that it may seem that way unless one looks more far closely at the details of those uses of words than one normally does. This close look at the details is roughly what he calls

“philosophical grammar”.36 It is because philosophers oppose such a close examination of the details that they are driven to posit hidden mechanisms to explain the genesis of meaningL. Thus, WittgensteinLP’s conclusion in PI (52) is that when one looks closely at the uses of words to see how meaningL does “arise” from ordinary linguistic usage the motivation for proposing hidden meaning-mechanisms evaporates.

Already Before Everyone’s Eyes

One is unable to notice something because it is always before one’s eyes.

Ludwig Wittgenstein, Philosophical Investigations (129)

God grant the philosopher insight into what lies in front of everyone’s eyes.

Ludwig Wittgenstein, Culture and Value (63)

Since WittgensteinLP holds that the genesis of meaningL is “already in plain view”37, he replaces causal/mechanical accounts of meaningL with a description of what everyone already knows—except when they are doing philosophy. He clarifies this with examples.

WittgensteinLP describes a “language-game” in which a sentence is expressed in an ordered set of names of coloured squares in a block itself composed of 3 lines of 3 smaller squares, i.e., “RGBGGGRWW” refers to a block in which the first square on the top left is red, the square to the immediate right of that one is green, the square to the immediate right of that one is black, and so on.38 The sign “R” in this “game” refers to a kind of red square that may occur anywhere in the three rows of three squares,

“B” refers to a kind of black square that may occur anywhere in the three rows of three squares, etc. What, WittgensteinLP asks, does it mean to say that “R,” in this “language-game,” means that kind of red square?

One common sort of answer is that “R” means that kind of red square because there is a causal connection between “R” and those sorts of red squares. Causal theories of meaning, tracing to Kripke’s causal theory of reference, explain the meaningL of a word by reference to the causal history of the word, how the word was introduced and transmitted, etc.39 One gets a different sort of causal account in the sorts of views that see language as produced by an internal meaning-mechanism. On Fodor’s

(8)

Journal for the Study of Religions and Ideologies, vol. 15, issue 43 (Spring 2016) 10 view, the meaningL of a word to organism O is determined by O’s internal representation of the semantic rules it follows in its linguistic behaviour—

where those internal representations are part of the causal determinants of the behaviour (e.g., Joe shows that he understands what Judy means when she shouts ‘Fire!” in a crowded theatre by rapidly exiting the building)40.

WittgensteinLP is generally opposed to causal theories of meaningL41, holding that such theories can only tell us how it comes about that words get used in a certain way—not what constitutes using those words meaningfullyL.42 So what does “going by the words” really consist in?

WittgensteinLP thinks we know the answer but have somehow forgotten it, If it is asked: “How do sentences manage to

represent?”—the answer might be: “Don’t you know? You certainly see it, when you use them.”

For nothing is concealed.43

Since we already know the answer, what is it? WittgensteinLP describes a “language-game” in which a person is to say “R” when they see a red square, “B” when they see a black one, etc.44 But if a person mistakenly says “R” when she sees a black square, “what is the criterion by which this is a mistake?” [LW’s emphasis] WittgensteinLP writes,

There are characteristic signs of [a mistake] in the player’s behaviour. Think of the behaviour charac- teristic of correcting a slip of the tongue. It would be possible to recognize that someone is doing so even without knowing his language.45

That is, part of what determines that “R” means the red square as opposed to the black one is the public criteria which determine that saying “R” when one sees a black square is a mistake.

Such criteria often include easily identifiable behaviour. Someone says, “That’s the breast bed I ever [pause] I mean [laughing] the best [heavy intonation] bed I ever slept in.” Thus, what one needs in such cases is not a theory linking words to the world but a description of the public criteria by which the linguistic community uses the words—and that is not something one only learns at Harvard but something one learns, so to speak, at one’s mothers knee. That is, “It is in language that it’s all done”.46 The same holds true for the language-game in which one correlates letters with coloured squares.

Fodor wants more. Surely something as sublime as meaningL cannot reside in anything so mundane as such everyday criteria but must rather be “realized” in some complicated internal mechanism. Others insist that the meaningL connection is constituted by some sublime connection between words and abstract objects.47 WittgensteinLP replies that, in fact, the meaningL connection is constituted by just such mundane matters.

(9)

Journal for the Study of Religions and Ideologies, vol. 15, issue 43 (Spring 2016) 11 For, he holds, the concept of meaningL is a concept pertaining to the public phenomena of human life. When one displaces this concept from its natural home into some alien context, such as neurophysiology or Platonic metaphysics no account satisfies—driving frustrated philosophers to ask: “Why is the theory of meaning so hard?”48

WittgensteinLP’s view is that it is hard because philosopher’s make it hard. Since the concept of meaningL is entirely foreign to such contexts nothing makes sense when it is imported into them from its natural home.

WittgensteinLP’s aim, therefore, is not to produce a new theory of meaningL. It is to describe how meaningL does, so to speak, “arise” out of those everyday mundane phenomena of everyday word-usage. The real challenge is not to produce some sophisticated new theory. It is to understand why doing philosophy makes one demand inappropriate sorts of “theories” that can never satisfy.

Recall Hume’s remark that when doing philosophy he finds himself in a deplorable condition, surrounded by “deepest darkness,” like some

“uncouth monster,” but that when he returns to the activities of common life his abstruse philosophical speculations appear “cold” and “ridicu- lous”.49 Hume sees that when doing philosophy the criteria deriving from one’s practical involvement in the world fall away—leaving him in darkness. Hume’s and WittgensteinLP’s shared remedy is a return to the everyday practical activities that are “always before one’s eyes.” In that everyday practical world, philosophical sophistications appear “ridicu- lous” because, in a certain sense, it is philosophizing itself that is the problem.

For, if Hume and WittgensteinLP are right, there is something about philosophizing that separates us from our natural home and makes us forget what we ordinarily know.50 It would seem that the philosopher, intoxicated by the sight of the unreachable stars, is in danger of falling into that well that was right before their eyes the whole time.51

Linguistic Meaning “from a Religious Point of View”

How do sentences [represent things]? Don’t you know? For nothing is hidden.

Ludwig Wittgenstein, Philosophical Investigations (435) [T]here is nothing hidden which will not become manifest.

The Gospel of Thomas (300)

It is, for reasons that become clear later, useful to examine Fodor’s criticism of “use-theories” of meaningL. Fodor holds that “use-theories” of meaningL “beg the question” because they hold that the fact that a word has the meaningL it does “reduces to the fact that we use it the way we do”

but no such reduction is plausible.52 Use-theories beg the questions because they presuppose a prior theory of meaningL. Consider an analogy:

(10)

Journal for the Study of Religions and Ideologies, vol. 15, issue 43 (Spring 2016) 12 A reduction requires a theory to be reduced, call it T1, and a theory, call it T2, to which T1 is to be reduced. One cannot reduce heat to the mean kinetic energy of molecules unless one has one theory T1 of the phenomenal heat and another theory T2 of the molecular entities to which T1 is to be reduced. Unfortunately, WittgensteinLP only gives a description of linguistic use and fails to provide a theory T1 of meaningL. Thus, WittgensteinLP wants to reduce meaningL to use but he neglects to provide the theory of meaningL which is to be reduced to use. WittgensteinLP is as foolish as a physicist who wants to reduce phenomenal heat to the mean kinetic energy of molecules but neglects to provide the theory of phenomenal heat that he wants to reduce to the molecular theory.

Fodor may be right that “use-theories” beg the question but WittgensteinLP, who holds that “we must not advance any kind of theory,”

never presents a use-theory.53 Since he does not provide any theories, he obviously cannot try to reduce one theory of meaning to another. Indeed, WittgensteinLP never uses the word “reduces” in this connection. It is no wonder that WittgensteinLP does not sketch the demanded reduction—for that reduction is required by Fodor’s theoretical paradigm, not WittgensteinLP’s. On WittgensteinLP’s paradigm it is more appropriate to talk about a “use-conception” than “use-theory.”

Fodor makes a related mistake in his critique of WittgensteinLP’s view, which he sees as a kind of behaviourism, of what it is to understand the meaningL of words.

[I]f anything is clear it is that understanding a word … isn’t a matter of how one behaves or [is]

disposed to behave. … [A]ny behaviour whatever is compatible with understanding or failing to understand any [word] … Pay me enough and I will stand on my head when you say ‘chair’. But I know what ‘chair’ means all the same.54

However, the fact that Fodor can be bribed to stand on his head when someone says “chair” has nothing to do with WittgensteinLP’s view of understanding words. WittgensteinLP’s notion of linguistic use is a normative notion that distinguishes proper from improper uses of words, where the former, not the latter, belong to “the use” of words.55 Wittgenstein’s account of what it is to understand words reflects that normative notion of use. Since Fodor’s bribed behaviour constitutes a misuse of the word, he only manages to refute a “misuse theory” of meaningL that no one defends, the view that the use (meaningL) of a word includes its misuses.

Indeed, Fodor himself tacitly acknowledges the need for a prior non- theoretical use-conception of meaningL when, responding to criticisms of his commitment to private Mentalese items, Fodor makes a curious admission: “We’ve all gotta use words when we talk”.56 That is, Fodor’s

(11)

Journal for the Study of Religions and Ideologies, vol. 15, issue 43 (Spring 2016) 13 theories may identify the meaningL of a word with a private “Mentalese”

item, but his theories about Mentalese items are stated in English—not Mentalese and one must possess a prior understanding of the use (meaningL) of those English words to understand his theories. Thus, when engaging in Hume’s activities of common life, Fodor knows what “chair”

meansL (how it is used) prior to any of the theories he concocts in his study.

However, despite the fact that Fodor admits, even if dismissively, that he presuppose a kind of linguistic know-how that is prior to his own mentalistic theory of meaningL, he seems, as WittgensteinLP predicts,57 blind to its significance. Why is Fodor loath to explore this prior stratum of meaningL which he admits we “gotta” use when stating his theories?58 He does want to provide a theory of the meaningL of the words we use when not in our studies … or doesn’t he?

Fodor is not interested in that prior domain of meaningL because he wants to explain it by reference to a more fundamental Mentalese language. But why does he want to explain it in that way? Recall Hume’s view that philosophizing has a way of rendering the philosopher-in-their- study as an “uncouth monster” in “the most deplorable condition” (world- less). Recall also Hume’s observation that the escape from that

“deplorable condition” does not require any new theories. Quite the contrary! It was such theories that were the problem. For those theories had separated him from his true home in the world of practical activities that had been “right before [his] eyes” the whole time. WittgensteinLP remarks that when doing philosophy “one must always ask oneself,”

[I]s the word ever actually used this way in the language-game which is its original home? What we do is bring words back from their metaphysical to their everyday use.59

Part of WittgensteinLP’s point here is that the escape from Fodor’s

“deplorable condition” is not difficult. One need only, following Hume, return to one’s true home in the world of human activities and the darkness vanishes. But why cannot Hume or Fodor see the path to their true home that lies just outside the door of their studies? This is, in fact, a perfect illustration of Wittgenstein’s point in WRD.

One powerful statement of this idea is found in the Gospel of Thomas:

“Jesus said: ‘Recognize that which is in your sight, and that which is hidden will become plain to you.’”60 What, precisely, will “become manifest”? The passage continues: “[I]f you will not know yourselves, you dwell in poverty and it is you who are that poverty.” In fact, the language of darkness, blindness and poverty in the Gospel of Thomas (and many other religious tracts) is found in the Preface to the Philosophical Investigations where WittgensteinLP describes the deplorable condition of his own age in these religious terms,

(12)

Journal for the Study of Religions and Ideologies, vol. 15, issue 43 (Spring 2016) 14 It is not impossible that it should fall to the lot of

this work, in its poverty and in the darkness of this time, to bring light into one brain or another—but

… it is not likely.

That is, the problem philosophers have “seeing” the truth is not a problem of intellect, leisure time, material conditions, discipline, etc. It is more like the problem that someone living in a state of sin (including

“philosophical sin”) has seeing the path to salvation that is “right before their eyes.” It is a problem of self-knowledge. The Gospel of Thomas continues,

I took my place in the midst of the world … I found all of them intoxicated;… [M]y soul became afflicted for the sons of men because they are blind in their hearts and do not have sight. … When they shake off their wine, then they will repent.61

The idea that the solution to philosophical problems is “always before one’s eyes” but that one fails to see it because one is in a state akin to “sin” (a lack of self-knowledge akin to intoxication) is unlikely to convince Fodor (and other philosophers-in-their-studies) to repent.

Indeed, WittgensteinLP criticized the teaching of professional philosophy (even his own), which makes “people drunk”.62 Fodor (and most main- stream philosophers) want theories of meaningL and theories of the under- standing of meaningL. WittgensteinLP’s point is that the price of such theories is blindness to the linguistic usage that one “gotta” presuppose in one’s true home that is already “right before [one’s] eyes”.

Malcolm and Winch are perplexed at WittgensteinLP’s point in WRD.

In fact, one of WittgensteinLP’s most fundamental religious images is found in the title of Malcolm’s book: Nothing is Hidden. This title is taken word for word from English translations of the gospels (see epigraph above).63 In the next sectionthis religious analogy is supplemented with a closely related ethical analogy from one of Wittgenstein’s revered religious authors: Dostoevsky.

An Ethical Analogy

He who despises most things will be a lawgiver among [the people] and he who dares most of all will be most in the right! … [One] must be blind not to see it.

Fyodor Dostoevsky, Crime and Punishment (Part V, Chap IV)

The way to solve the problem you see in life is to live in a way that will Make what is problematic disappear.

Ludwig Wittgenstein, Culture and Value (27)

(13)

Journal for the Study of Religions and Ideologies, vol. 15, issue 43 (Spring 2016) 15 Since WittgensteinLP was impressed by religious and moral themes in Dostoevsky64, an example from Crime and Punishment is illuminating. The claim is not that WittgensteinLP’s view of the sense in which the solution to philosophical problems is right before one’s eyes is precisely the same as the sense in which the solution to moral problems is right before one’s eyes, but only that there is a useful clarifying analogy between these.65

In Crime and Punishment, Raskolnikov, a former student, inflated with pride, and motivated by a feeling that he is fated to immoral acts but also by certain “philosophical theories”, decides to kill an unpleasant old lady.66 He kills her, but also kills her sister who just happened on the scene, with an axe. Raskolnikov’s “philosophical theory”, reminiscent of Nietzsche’s theory of a Master race, is that for the Masters “all is permitted”,67 i.e., the Masters are not bound by ordinary moral laws. Soon after the murder Raskolnikov becomes feverish and begins behaving strangely—as if he wants to be caught. Nevertheless, he appears to commit the perfect crime. He befriends a woman named Sonya, filled with Christian virtue but who had been forced into prostitution by desperate circumstances. He confesses to Sonya, who urges him to confess to the police, and, eventually, he does so. He is sentenced to 8 years of penal servitude in Siberia. Sonya follows him to await his release, and eventually, with Sonya’s love, he achieves redemption.

A central theme of the story is that most people are blind to the path to salvation that lies right before their eyes. Raskolnikov had been blinded by his proud philosophical theories into believing that he was superior to moral laws. But there is another view about who is really blind. Sonia states that Jesus could have miraculously saved a man from death and made even “the blind disbelieving Jews” believe.68 So is it the proud

“philosopher” with theories in his/her head or the humble prostitute with Christian love in his/her heart that is really blind? Porfiry, a policeman on Raskolnikov’s trail, in an attempt to rattle him, describes the plight of modern man (i.e., he describes Raskolnikov) to Raskolnikov: “Here we have bookish dreams, a heart unhinged by theories”.69 Porfiry’s view, reminiscent of WittgensteinLP’s views, is that the truth resides in the pure heart but that the heart is often misled by proud theories into failing to see what is right before one’s eyes.

After being imprisoned, Raskolnikov adjusts to a bare convict existence with no hope or companionship and becomes sullen, self- absorbed, irritated by Sonya’s visits, even rude to her.70 Eventually, he changes but it is not “the horrors of prison life” (i.e., not his

“punishment”) that change him.71 Those “horrors” are not the path to salvation. Raskolnikov’s transformation comes when, after Sonya disappears for a time due to illness, she re-appears, “still appearing ill, thin and pale.” Seeing her in that state, “something seemed to seize”

Raskolnikov and “fling him at her feet,”

(14)

Journal for the Study of Religions and Ideologies, vol. 15, issue 43 (Spring 2016) 16 They were both pale and thin; but those sick pale

faces were bright with the dawn of a new future, of a full resurrection into a new life. They were renewed by love; the heart of each held infinite sources of life for the heart of the other.72

The breakthrough is Raskolnikov’s loss of pride. Once he abandons his sinful pride and lowers himself to her feet he is “resurrected” into “a new life”—whereupon everything changes. His sentence too (seven years) suddenly seems different than it had a day earlier:

Seven years, only seven years! At the beginning of their happiness at some moments they were both ready to look on those seven years as though they were seven days.73

Since it took the Christian God seven days to create the world, this signifies that Raskolnikov’s redemption is the creation of a new man and a transition to a new world,

[T]hat is the beginning of a new story—the story of the gradual renewal of a man, … his gradual regeneration, … his passing from one world into another,…74

The solution to Raskolnikov’s problems does not involve any new facts or theories. In fact, the solution had been there all along but, blinded by his pride, he had been unable to see it. It is the humble prostitute with love in her heart, not the proud philosopher with his/her theories, who can see what is “always before [one’s] eyes.” WittgensteinLP agrees: “The edifice of your pride has to be dismantled. And that is terribly hard work”.75 The seven years that lay before him yesterday still lays before him today.

Yesterday it was a seven years of living death. Today it is “only seven years!” The facts are the same, but Raskolnikov has “learned to live in a way that makes the problem disappear.” That new way of living (new form of life) requires abandoning the proud theories that had led to a bloody corpse, his feverish state, Sonya’s suffering and the meaningless existence of a convict.

In a sense, therefore, WittgensteinLP’s Philosophical Investigations describes the poverty and darkness that results from the philosopher’s intoxication with their proud theories of language and mind. The claim is not that the philosopher literally commits a sin of pride. WittgensteinLP’s claim in WRD is that looking at philosophical problems from this religious point of view suggests the way to dissolve these problems and return to one’s more humble true “home” in forms of human life. Just as Raskolnikov must abandon his proud theories in order to see the new path to salvation that had been right before his eyes the whole time, philosophers must abandon their proud theories about meaningL and

(15)

Journal for the Study of Religions and Ideologies, vol. 15, issue 43 (Spring 2016) 17 learn to see the more humble sort of meaningL that Fodor admits we’ve

“gotta” use when not in our studies.

Wittgenstein: Not a Religious Man?

I think the question whether Wittgenstein was a ‘religious person’ is even more difficult than I realized when I [originally] wrote the Memoir [in 1958].

Norman Malcolm, Ludwig Wittgenstein: A Memoir (80)

In WRD WittgensteinLP only states that he uses religious points of view as a tool for gaining a new perspective on philosophical problems76, but that is separate from the question whether Wittgenstein is himself a religious person. One might expect that if he finds it useful to look at philosophical problems from a religious point of view this must reflect some religious dimension in his own life—which coheres with his remark in the Forward to PR that he would like to dedicate the book to the glory of God. On the other hand, it contradicts his subsidiary remark in WRD that he is “not a religious man”.77 That subsidiary remark, in turn, accords with von Wright’s view that Wittgenstein could not be said to be religious in any but a trivial sense of the word.78 It would seem that, like so many other things about this very complicated person, there are no simple an- swers here. Thus, any account of Wittgenstein’s own religious dimension must be carefully nuanced. But before tackling this question, it is first necessary to ask what it means to say that one is “a religious man.”

First, by saying that S is a religious person, one might mean that S adheres to certain religious doctrines, e.g., S believes that God exists. Call this the “Intellectualist Criterion” or IC! However, since Wittgenstein holds that Christianity is not a body of doctrine and that the gospels might even be false without undermining their religious importance,79 he is not religious in IC’s sense. Furthermore, there are people who accept religious doctrines on intellectual grounds but are not religious at all, e.g., Richard Gale holds that the Gale-Pruss cosmological argument for the existence of God actually works80, but Gale stresses that has no personal interest whatsoever in such questions.81 IC does not state either a necessary or a sufficient for genuine religiosity.

One might also be said to be religious in the weaker sense that one is influenced by certain religious points of view. Call this the “Religious- Influence Criterion” or RIC! Since Wittgenstein was clearly influenced by religious thinkers such as Augustine and Kierkegaard,82 there is no doubt that he was religious in RIC’s sense, but this is a very minimal kind of religiosity. The very religious Hegel heavily influenced Marx and yet the latter could not be called religious in any significant sense. Further, it seems clear that von Wright is hasty in claiming that Wittgenstein can

(16)

Journal for the Study of Religions and Ideologies, vol. 15, issue 43 (Spring 2016) 18 only be called religious in a trivial sense. Whereas Malcolm had earlier agreed with Von Wright that Wittgenstein is not a religious person,83 Malcolm changed his view after he became aware of Wittgenstein’s remarks on religion eventually published in CV. Malcolm acknowledges that many remarks in CV are “religious thoughts” or bear “a religious stamp”.84 In one such remark, Wittgenstein alludes to a third sense in which one can be religious, namely that one is religious to the extent that one’s religious views lead one to “change … the direction of your life”.85 Call this the “Religious Transformation Criterion” or RTC! In a passage somewhat reminiscent of passages in Kierkegaard, Wittgenstein writes,

[R]eligious belief could only be something like a passionate commitment to a system of reference.

Hence, although it’s a belief, it’s really a way of living, a way of assessing life. Instruction in religious faith, therefore, would have to [involve]

an appeal to conscience.86

Since RTC is Wittgenstein’s own criterion for genuine religiosity, it is clear why he states in WRD that he is “not a religious man.” Wittgenstein leads the life of a philosopher, not that of a prophet or saint. He does not make RTC’s passionate commitment to a religious “system”. Thus, Malcolm was correct that “If ‘to be a religious person’ is to ‘lead a religious life’ then … [Wittgenstein] was not a religious person”.87 It is, however, important to recognize why Wittgenstein does not satisfy RTC. Malcolm had remarked that Wittgenstein understood “religious belief [to be] based on qualities of character and will that he himself did not possess.”88 Malcolm goes on in the same passage to report that those close to Wittgenstein had to see that he felt “that our lives are dark and ugly—a feeling that was often close to despair.” Thus, if Wittgenstein is not religious, the fault does not lie with religion. It lies with himself. This is why Malcolm acknowledged that though Wittgenstein was not a religious person, he seemed to acknowledge “the possibility of religion”.89 That is, even in his early Memoir Malcolm understood that even if Wittgenstein felt that he is himself personally too flawed to be genuinely religious, Wittgenstein still felt that there remains the possibility that people might become religious via an “appeal to conscience”. 90

Wittgenstein cites the Pauline doctrine of predestination as an example of one of the religious doctrines that may be too high for him,

[A]t my level, the Pauline doctrine of predestination is ugly nonsense, irreligiousness.

Hence it is not suitable for me … If it is a good and godly picture, then it is for someone at a quite different level ….91

(17)

Journal for the Study of Religions and Ideologies, vol. 15, issue 43 (Spring 2016) 19 In keeping with RTC, Wittgenstein can say that such doctrines may be “godly” even as he admits that he is not himself at the level to be transformed by them.

It is now possible to understand why Wittgenstein says in WRD that he is “not a religious man” but also why there are “religious thoughts” in his writings. First, Wittgenstein is not a religious man by virtue of his method in WRD. WRD only states that he uses religious views to gain new philosophical perspectives but that is completely independent of the question whether he is personally religious or not. Second, Wittgenstein is not a religious man in the sense that he does not subscribe to religious doctrines (because he holds that genuine religiosity does not consist in intellectual assent to doctrines). Third, and perhaps more important, he is not a religious man in the sense that he does not lead a religious life (because he believes that he is too imperfect to lead a genuine religious life). However, all this is all consistent with the fact that his work contains

“religious thoughts”. For, Wittgenstein statement that he is “not a religious man” is, in fact, the statement that he himself falls short of genuine religiosity because he is incapable of transforming his life in accord with such religious thoughts. Wittgenstein can admire genuine religiosity from afar (from the vantage point of the philosopher), and he can even wish that he could enter into genuine religiosity, but this is something of which he feels personally incapable.

This puts the earlier criticisms of Malcolm, Winch, and Labron in a new light. Although Malcolm et al misrepresent the philosophical claim in WRD, there turns out to be an important element of truth in their readings. The reason Malcolm et al go wrong in their readings of WRD is that they correctly feel something akin to religious views and/or passions (or at least a deep respect for these sorts of views and passions) in WittgensteinLP’s writings (the “religious thoughts” eventually Malcolm came to see in Wittgenstein). For even if WittgensteinLP is not religious by his own criterion (RTC), someone who holds genuine religiosity in such esteem and despairs at his own inability to rise to such religiosity would be judged to be religious by a great many ordinary people. Indeed, Franz Parak, with whom Wittgenstein was friends in the German prisoner of war camp, states that Wittgenstein would have most liked to become a priest and read the Bible with children.92 It is for such reasons that Malcolm et al find it easy to read those religious views or passions mistakenly into the philosophical claim in WRD. That is, even though Malcolm, Winch, and Labron may get the “letter” of WRD wrong they may get important aspects of the “spirit” of the WittgensteinianLP text right. The respect for the genuine religious they feel in his writings is there—but it is imperative not to mistake the yearning for genuine religiosity by the self-admitted imperfect person who feels himself incapable of it with the mere philosophical tool that he describes in WRD.

(18)

Journal for the Study of Religions and Ideologies, vol. 15, issue 43 (Spring 2016) 20

Notes:

1 References to Wittgenstein’s works are as follows, to the Tractatus by proposition number, to Culture and Value by page number, to On Certainty by paragraph number, to Philosophical Investigations by paragraph number or by page number as appropriate, to Philosophical Grammar and Remarks on the Foundations of Mathematics by section and paragraph number, to Lecture on Religious Belief by section number.

References to all other works are, unless otherwise indicated, by page number.

2 Norman Malcolm, Wittgenstein: From a Religious Point of View? (New York:

Routledge, 1997), 1. Wittgenstein’s claim that he cannot help looking at philosophical problems from a religious point of view is the main claim in WRD.

His subsidiary remark in WRD that he is “not a religious man” is treated separately in the final section of the paper.

3 By Wittgenstein’s later philosophy is meant his Philosophical Investigations, Remarks on the Foundations of Mathematics, On Certainty, and Culture and Value. By his early philosophy is meant his Tractatus. His Philosophical Remarks and Philosophical Grammar are transitional works. Although it is difficult to draw the distinction between Wittgenstein’s “early” and “later” philosophies with precision, WittgensteinLP did distinguish sharply between his early and later ways of looking at things. See Saul Kripke, Wittgenstein on Rules and Private Language (Cambridge:

Harvard University Press, 1982), 78, 120, 123.

4 Wittgenstein, Philosophical Investigations, 89.

5 Philip Shields, Logic and Sin in the Writings of Ludwig Wittgenstein (Chicago:

University of Chicago Press, 1993); Norman Malcolm, Wittgenstein: From a Religious Point of View; Peter Winch, “Discussion of Malcolm’s Essay,”in Wittgenstein: From a Religious Point of View?, ed. Norman Malcolm, (New York: Routledge, 1997), 95- 136; Tim Labron, Wittgenstein’s Religious Point of View (London/New York:

Continuum, 2006).

6 Wittgenstein, Philosophical Investigations, 126, 129, 435; Compare with Heidegger’s notion of the phenomenology as the letting something be seen as “unhidden”.

Martin Heidegger, Being and Time (San Francisco: HarperSanFrancisco, 1962) § 7, B-C.

7 Philip Shields, Logic and Sin in the Writings of Ludwig Wittgenstein.

8 Wittgenstein, Philosophical Investigations, 108; See also David Pears, The False Prison, vol. 2, (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1988),384-85.

9 Tim Labron, Wittgenstein’s Religious Point of View, 2.

10 Anthony Kenny, “Wittgenstein on the Nature of Philosophy,”in Wittgenstein and His Times, ed. Anthony Kenny & Brian McGuinness, (England: Thommes Press, 1982), 15; Ray Monk, Ludwig Wittgenstein: The Duty of Genius (New York: Penguin, 1990), 416; Chrysoulia Gitsoulis, “The Moral Dimension of Wittgenstein’s

Philosophical Method,” Analysis and Metaphysics 6 (2006): 452-467,

http://www.academia.edu/351053/_2007_The_Moral_Dimension_of_Wittgenstei ns_Philosophical_Method.

11 Norman Malcolm, Wittgenstein: From a Religious Point of View, 92. See also Peter Winch, “Discussion of Malcolm’s Essay”, 110.

12 Peter Winch, 97.

13 Peter Winch, 97, 112.

14 Peter Winch, 97.

(19)

Journal for the Study of Religions and Ideologies, vol. 15, issue 43 (Spring 2016) 21

15 Milton Diamond, “Transsexuality Among Twins: Identity Concor¬dance, Transition, Rearing, and Orientation,” International Journal of Transgenderism 14:1 (2013): 24-38.

16 One might think such examples are unfair since Malcolm is clearly referring to ultimate explanations, not the sort of provisional explanations one might find in social psychology. However, as Peter Winch (“Discussion of Malcolm’s Essay”, 111-112), points out, Malcolm holds that all language-games are “beyond explanation.”

17 G.H. Hardy, Collected Papers of G. H. Hardy, vol. 7. (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1979), 720.

18 Robert Kanigel, The Man who knew Infinity (S. Scribner’s, 1991), 27.

19 Jeffrey Kottler, Divine Madness: Ten Stories of Creative Struggle (Hoboken, NJ: Jossey- Bass, 2005).

20 Ludwig Wittgenstein, Philosophical Investigations, 255, 593.

21 Max Fink, Electroconvulsive Therapy (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2008), 92, 100.

22 Peter Winch, “Discussion of Malcolm’s Essay”, 132.

23 Peter Winch, 106.

24 Peter Winch, 124-132.

25 Ray Monk, The Duty of Genius, 310.

26 Peter Winch, “Discussion of Malcolm’s Essay”, 129.

27 Tim Labron, Wittgenstein’s Religious Point of View, 3-5, 99ff.

28 Tim Labron, 74.

29 O.K. Bouwsma, Wittgenstein: Conversations 1949–1951 (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1986), 61.

30 Peter Winch, “Discussion of Malcolm’s Essay”, 108.

31 Immanuel Kant, Grounding for the Metaphysics of Morals (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1993), 30.

32 Similarly, by his “intentional stance” (intentional “point of view”), Dennett does not mean that living organisms actually have organic states that are analogous to intentions. He means that they do not—but that it is sometimes useful to look at them as if they do. See Daniel Dennett in The Intentional Stance (Cambridge: MIT, 1996).

33 Wittgenstein, Philosophical Investigations, 52.

34 Wittgenstein, Philosophical Investigations, 51.

35 SeeRichard McDonough, “Wittgenstein’s Augustinian Cosmogony in Zettel 608,”

Philosophy and Literature 39 (1) (2015): 89-92.

36 Wittgenstein, Philosophical Investigations, 664.

37 Ludwig Wittgenstein, 89.

38 Ludwig Wittgenstein, 48.

39 Saul Kripke, Naming and Necessity; Jeff Speaks, “Theories of Meaning”, in Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, 2014, http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/meaning/, § 3.2.2.

40 This formulation refers to “speakers meaning” as opposed to “sentence meaning”, but Fodor tells a related but not identical story about meaningL. See Jerry Fodor, The Language of Thought (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1979), 104 n3, 116 n 12; Jerry Fodor, Psychosemantics. The Problem of Meaning in the Philosophy of Mind (Cambridge: MIT, 1987), x-xi, 135ff.

41 Ludwig Wittgenstein, Philosophical Grammar: V, 64; Ludwig Wittgenstein, Philosophical Investigations, 89; Ludwig Wittgenstein, Culture and Value, 37; Ludwig

(20)

Journal for the Study of Religions and Ideologies, vol. 15, issue 43 (Spring 2016) 22 Wittgenstein, Remarks on the Foundations of Mathematics, III, 41; V.15; Ray Monk, The Duty of Genius, 291.

42 Anthony Kenny, Wittgenstein, 52.

43 Ludwig Wittgenstein, Philosophical Investigations, 435.

44 Ludwig Wittgenstein, 51.

45 Ludwig Wittgenstein, 54.

46 Ludwig Wittgenstein Philosophical Grammar, VII, 9; See also Ludwig Wittgenstein, On Certainty, 3.

47 Jerrold Katz, Language and Other Abstract Objects (Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield, 1981), 3-4, 9, 221.

48 Hilary Putnam, Mind, Language and Reality, v. 2 (New York: Cambridge, 1979), 139.

49 David Hume, A Treatise of Human Nature (Oxford: The Clarendon Press, 1967), 264, 269.

50 WittgensteinLP exposes the artificial character of many philosophical examples.

See Ludwig Wittgenstein, Philosophical Investigations, 349; Ludwig Wittgenstein, On Certainty, 3, 6, 10! In his class lectures Wilfrid Sellars used to pick up a book from a student’s desk and ask, “How do I know this is not a reefer box?” In fact, he knew full well it was a book because he had just seen a student reading it—illustrating the fact that many philosophical examples seem completely divorced from genuine contexts of usage.

51 Reginald Allen, Thales to Aristotle (New York: The Free Press, 1966), 28.

52 Jerry Fodor, Psychosemantics, 160 n 6.

53 Ludwig Wittgenstein, Philosophical Investigations, 109.

54 Jerry Fodor, The Language of Thought, 63

55 Ludwig Wittgenstein, Philosophical Investigations, 81

56 Jerry Fodor, The Language of Thought, 121.

57 Ludwig Wittgenstein, Philosophical Investigations, 129.

58 It is worth asking why Fodor feels the need admit something that is “always before everyone’s eyes”. See Ludwig Wittgenstein, Philosophical Investigations, 128!

59 Ludwig Wittgenstein, Philosophical Investigations, 116.

60 The Gospel of Thomas, 300. Note that the Biblical quotes used in the present paper are employed as examples of religious views. No stand on their truth or falsity is implied by their use here.

61 The Gospel of Thomas, 307.

62 Ray Monk, The Duty of Genius, 555.

63 See also Samuel 8:13, Psalms 9:16; Chronicles 9:2; 1 Kings 10:3; 1; Matthew 10:26;

Mark 4:22; Luke 8:17, 12:2; Corinthians 4:5; Acts 26:6. URL:

http://biblehub.net/search.php?q=nothing+hidden. Nor is the idea limited to the Jewish and Christian parts of the Bible but it is also found in the Quran. See Maulana Muhammad Ali, trans, The Holy Quran with English Translation and Commentary (Lahore: Ahamadiyya Anjuman Ishaat Islam, 2002), 20, 22! Similar ideas also found in Buddhist scripture. See Donald Lopez, editor, Buddhist Scripture (New York: Penguin, 2004), 104, 465, 517! The idea that once one achieves spiritual enlightenment is achieved “nothing is hidden” from one is an idea common to many different religions.

64 Norman Malcolm, Notes added in 1985 to Ludwig Wittgenstein: A Memoir, 19, 45;

Ray Monk, The Duty of Genius, 136.

65 See G.H. Von Wright, preface to Culture and Value, by Ludwig Wittgenstein (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1980).

Referințe

DOCUMENTE SIMILARE

(1 st generation female); (2) The role of women [in traditional South Asian culture] is about sitting at home, rais- ing children, being a housewife, and just cooking food for

Each unique religious orientation (i.e., extrinsic, intrinsic, quest, and orthodox) is associated with specific social outcomes, and determining the distinguishing features of

The chairman of the Education and Instruction Board of the Turkish National Ministry, which is responsible for curricula at the national level, responded to critics

They present evidence that cultural differences between Japan and the US and the confidence of pa- rents about their worldviews explain the differences in child discipline

“Crimes Committed by Totalitarian Regimes.” 30 Taking advantage of the European Union Presidency’s being held by four former communist.. Journal for the Study

According to Codoban, the anthropology presented by the author perfectly resembles Stăniloae’s theological traits, with the individual and the communion being placed at

Although the document does not pay much attention to corruption, it nevertheless draws attention to it and names the activities that destroy the social and personal life

Different from other scholars who view Confucianism as a religious tradition, Heiner Roetz considers Confucianism mainly as “a non- conformist and basically

By using credibility as a mode of persuasion adds to the element of Ethos (Murthy and Ghosal 2014). All these are done for one purpose, which is to highlight the government’s

Ecology is the study of the relationships between living organisms, including humans, and their physical environment; it seeks to understand the vital connections between

Sandu Frunză’s book Între moartea politicii și moartea lui Dumnezeu [Between the Death of Politics and the Death of God], subtitled Eseuri despre literatură, religie şi

18, issue 53 (Summer 2019) 85 The line graph in Figure 1 shows similarities and differences in patterns of variation of religiosity by fields of study across the

However, the sphere is topologically different from the donut, and from the flat (Euclidean) space.. Classification of two

As an existential stylist, the philosopher reveals, through his analysis, the benefits that philosophical counselling can bring inside the relationship between

Due to the fact that materialism leads to life dissatisfaction, a solution to increase happiness is to decrease materialism, thus people to be less surrounded by objects

Although Carlbom (2003) and others zealously criticize the state for its perceived inability to welcome radically different social norms, they at the same time

Superpanopticism which, according to Žižek’s (2003, 255-267) paradigm, fuels the simulacrum of power games, is an arena where the marginal political actors (used by

In order to remove this serious threat I have tried to prove that to some extent tradition already embodies the interests of all individuals (whether they belong to

The ideas of Erich Fromm and Eastern Orthodoxy are both based on a perception of a human being as a distinct whole personality, who should perceive as basic

The study acknowledging that indigenous cultures and systems have been eroded by the advent of foreign religions that use financial and material resources as bait,

This study examines the role of marketing by churches as non-profit organisations in fulfilling their social responsibility.. A qualitative methodology was used to

In particular, when all unit root tests are performed with only an intercept then the unit root hypothesis is rejected across all the time series variables at

– Players, Objectives, Procedures, Rules, Resources, Conflict, Boundaries, Outcome. •